Skip to main content

Art Fights: The Persistence of Controversy in Modern Aesthetics

  • Chapter
Outrage: Art, Controversy, and Society
  • 301 Accesses

Abstract

It seems the “diversity in judgment” to which Hume refers is more the rule than the exception, that our “contrary sentiments” about aesthetic matters are inevitable and controversy endemic to the field of the arts.1 Indeed, Hume’s standard of taste does not just happen to evade us in certain instances; rather, where taste is involved, we necessarily seek out—and inevitably fail to find—the grounds for universal assent. This much has already been argued. As I discuss below, Kant, in his critique of empiricist aesthetics, identified the standard of taste as fundamentally elusive, sought every time we make a claim about beauty.2 What is less obvious in Kant’s articulation of the thesis is that the nature of this collective search is essentially contentious. For it is not shared taste, a common standard, that unites dissenting voices, but the fact of dissent itself and the fact of controversy: we fight about art, therefore “we” are.

The general principles of taste are uniform in human nature: Where men vary in their judgments, some defect or perversion in the faculties may commonly be remarked; proceeding either from prejudice, from want of practice, or want of delicacy: and there is just reason for approving one taste, and condemning another. But where there is such a diversity in the internal frame or external situation as is entirely blameless on both sides, and leaves no room to give one the preference above the other; in that case a certain degree of diversity in judgment is unavoidable, and we seek in vain for a standard, by which we can reconcile the contrary sentiments.

David Hume, “Of the Standard of Taste” (1757)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Pierre Bourdieu, Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgment of Taste, trans. Richard Nice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984), p. 493.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Jonathan Loesberg, “Bourdieu’s Derrida’s Kant: The Aesthetics of Refusing Aesthetics,” Modern Language Quarterly, 58:4 (December 1997), pp. 417–436, at p. 418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Richard Hooker, Dominic Paterson, and Paul Stirton, “Bourdieu and the Art Historians,” in Reading Bourdieu on Society and Culture, ed. Bridget Fowler (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000), pp. 212–228, at p. 217.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Robert Holton, “Bourdieu and Common Sense,” in Pierre Bourdieu: Fieldwork in Culture, eds. Nicholas Brown and Imre Szeman (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2000), pp. 94–95.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Koenraad Geldof, “Authority, Reading, Reflexivity: Pierre Bourdieu and the Aesthetic Judgment of Kant,” Diacritics, 27:1 (1997), pp. 20–43, at p. 24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Kojin Karatani, Transcritique on Kant and Marx (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2003), p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Michel Foucault, Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology, ed. James D. Faubion, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: New Press, 1998), p. 320.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Bourdieu exaggerates the subjectivism of Kant and the objectivism of Foucault. Kant, as I have mentioned already (and as I develop below), continually rejected what he saw as the subjectivism of the rationalists, while Foucault, who was never comfortable with the label “structuralist,” was less invested in the primacy of discourse than Bourdieu suggests. See, for example, Foucault, et al., Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with Michel Foucault (Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press, 1988), p. 9; or, for a more unequivocal remark about the label, see Foucault, Aesthetics, p. 437, where Foucault states, “I have never been a Freudian, I have never been a Marxist, and I have never been a structuralist.”

    Google Scholar 

  9. Hannah Arendt, Between Past and Future (New York: Penguin, 1993), p. 222.

    Google Scholar 

  10. On the distinction between these two adages, see Luc Ferry, Homo Aestheticus: The Invention of Taste in the Democratic Age (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1993), pp. 48–53.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgement, trans. James Creed Meredith (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973), p. 338.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Hannah Arendt, Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, ed. Ronald Beiner (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1982), p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2012 Manu Samriti Chander

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Chander, M.S. (2012). Art Fights: The Persistence of Controversy in Modern Aesthetics. In: Howells, R., Ritivoi, A.D., Schachter, J. (eds) Outrage: Art, Controversy, and Society. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137283542_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics