Skip to main content

Hegel’s Philosophy of History and Kierkegaard’s Concept of History: A Synthesis Instead of a Confrontation

  • Chapter
Kierkegaard on the Philosophy of History
  • 164 Accesses

Abstract

My aim in this chapter will be threefold: (a) to give a more elaborate synopsis of Hegel’s claims on the nature of history and a similar more elaborate analysis of the Kierkegaardian concept of history drawing on my conclusions from the previous three chapters (b) to argue in favour of a synthesis of their points of view rather than view them only as direct philosophical opponents or treating their philosophies on history as totally and utterly incompatible, and (c) to explain and analyse the reasons that make me believe that all the past positions regarding their relations are either partly or totally flawed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Hegel’s ‘Reason’ is not a static logical activity. As Arthur Berndtson argues: ‘reason for Hegel is not fixed and detached; it is an immanent process, which creates the logic, nature and mind.’ Arthur Berndtson, ‘Hegel, Reason and Reality’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 20, No. 1 (September 1959), p. 44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Reason then must fulfil this historical task: to direct human communi ties into a specific political state that will provide the necessary conditions for the members of these communities to become free. Hegel’s PR shows emphatically Hegel’s view on how people can be ‘free’ and what the exact meaning of their ‘freedom’ is. As J. A. Leighton states: ‘Freedom is the Idea of Spirit... All the struggles of nations and individuals are stepping-stones by which men rise to freedom. J. A. Leighton, ‘Hegel’s Conception of God’, The Philosophical Review, Vol. 5, No. 6 (November 1896), p. 611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Hegel believes that, if we try to view history purely as an activity of single human beings, we will eventually end in a totally chaotic and meaningless historical universe. Social and ethical institutions and mainly organised states can guarantee us (in Hegel’s view) the necessary ‘objectivity’. S. W. Dyde in ‘Hegel’s Conception of Freedom’, The Philosophical Review, Vol. 3, No. 6, (November 1894), p. 664

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Donald J. Maletz in ‘History in Hegel’s Philosophy of Right’, The Review of Politics, Vol. 45, No. 2 (April 1983), p. 222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, translated by T. M. Knox, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1952), p. 13.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. As Richard Kroner states it in his introduction to Hegel’s Early Theological Writings: ‘It is true that Hegel believed in the historical process as divinely ordained... History is shaped by Providence, and Providence is Reason and can therefore be understood by the speculative dialectic of the philosopher. From this conviction a certain quietism resulted, satisfaction with actual conditions, and submissiveness to the universal will — not of the state but of the world... Not party politics nor class prejudice, but metaphysical fervor determines his views.’ Kroner, ‘Introduction’ in G. W. F. Hegel, Early Theological Writings, translated by T. M. Knox, with an Introduction, and Fragments translated by Richard Kroner, (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1985), p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  7. As Stephen Crites points out: ‘The “existing individual”, an irreducibly temporal being, confronts an open future which he must determine by his own decision about himself.’ Stephen Crites, In the Twilight of Christendom: Hegel vs Kierkegaard on Faith and History, (Pennsylvania: American Academy of Religion, 1972), p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg (1802–1872) was a critic of Hegelianism. He was mainly interested in Aristotle’s work in Logic (De Aristotelis categoriis). See Dario Gonzalez’s analysis in: ‘Trendelenburg: An Ally against Speculation’, from Kierkegaard and His German Contemporaries, Tome I: Philosophy, edited by Jon Stewart, (Hampshire: Ashgate, 2007), pp. 309–334.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Mark C. Taylor says something similar when he argues that: ‘it can be said that for Kierkegaard temporality is the form of human existence.’ Mark C. Taylor, ‘Time’s Struggle with Space: Kierkegaard’s Understanding of Temporality’, The Harvard Theological Review, Vol. 66, No. 3 (July 1973), p. 329.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Niels Thulstrup, Kierkegaard’s Relation to Hegel, translated by George L. Stengren, (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1980), p. 355.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Jean-Paul Sartre, Between Existentialism and Marxism, translated by John Mathews, (New York: Morrow Quill Paperbacks, 1979)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Mark C. Taylor, Journeys to Selfhood, Hegel & Kierkegaard, (New York: Fordham University Press, 2000), p. ix.

    Google Scholar 

  13. James Bogen, ‘Remarks on the Kierkegaardian-Hegel Controversy’, Synthese, (Vol. 13, No 4, December 1961), pp. 372–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Peter J. Mehl, Thinking through Kierkegaard, Existential Identity in a Pluralistic World, (Urbana and Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 2005).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Merold Westphal, Kierkegaard’s Critique of Reason and Society, (Pennsylvania: he Pennsylvania State University Press, 1991)

    Google Scholar 

  16. P. Christopher Smith, ‘Hegel, Kierkegaard, and the Problem of Finitude’, in Hegel, History, and Interpretation, edited by Shaun Gallagher, (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997), p. 226.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Hegel, Early Theological Writings, translated by T. M. Knox; with an introduction, and fragments translated by Richard Kroner, (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971), p. 175.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Soren Kierkegaard, Prefaces, Writing Sampler, edited and translated by Todd W. Nichol, (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1997), p. 58

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2014 Georgios Patios

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Patios, G. (2014). Hegel’s Philosophy of History and Kierkegaard’s Concept of History: A Synthesis Instead of a Confrontation. In: Kierkegaard on the Philosophy of History. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137383280_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics